One of the most pernicious aspects of our thought-lives is the idea of balance—the expectation that this or that element ought to have a corresponding opposing element. Unsurprisingly, this leads to difficulties in the realm of religion, where mundane pairings like light and dark, past and future, alien and familiar, and the like, run up against much more troubling pairings—most famously, good and evil.
We see good as the counterpoint to evil, and yet the very
idea of a latent “balance” is of course troubling to us. Good must be greater than evil. (And evil must be cast into an intellectual
realm in which—contrary to our most “logical” tendencies—evil must be thought
somehow separate from the creative will of God, and yet evil could not create
itself, and so on.) It must be asked first
and foremost if the dualistic concept of counterbalancing opposites is not an
imposition of us onto our conceptions of existence, rather than a necessary
concept.
It might be asked, for example, how life can be the opposite
of death. Life experiences death, but
death does not experience life. Death
does not come to life, yet life comes to death.
Inescapably, “death” as an object of consideration occurs only to that
which is living, while yet it is only the living that also experiences “life” as
an object of consideration.
Or to put it in a more general way (as I believe philosophers
have done, more artfully than I), that which exists can both exist and be
understood as no longer existing, but that which does not exist cannot in
counterbalance be thought to intrude into the realm of existence. Or something like that—I find it all rather
confusing.
What ought not to be confusing is the way in which we must
cede to God the ability to make things exist or not at will. Genesis describes God as speaking Creation
into existence and then calling Creation “good.” Creation is less than God, and therefore by necessity
uncategorizable as possessing the full range of divine perfections. Creation is “good,” but it is not “perfect,”
and therefore Creation could be called “not good” by God, if he so willed.
What might be stated just as bluntly, however, is that God
could will out of existence any or all of the “not goodness” of Creation. He is God, after all. This is probably behind the great irony of
the “Fall” episode. Adam and Eve are
raised above the animals in “knowing” good and evil—though the “above” part is
ironic in itself, since arguably animals know good and evil in terms of what to
approach and what to avoid—Adam and Eve simply acquired the chance to be
philosophical, judgmental, unforgiving, and wrong in their notions of what to
approach and what to avoid.
Moreover, it is only in a partial sense that humanity “knowing
good and evil” makes humanity “like God,” in that humanity is in no way promised
thereby God’s sovereign prerogative to will the good or evil of this or that
out of existence. To put it another way,
the God that can “know” (as much as “will” or “speak” or any other presumptuous
verb thrust by us onto him) anything into existence can also “know” that thing
into a greater or lesser moral state.
The most intellectually volatile aspect of any concept of
dualism must be the inherent tension between dualism and the sovereignty of the
Creator God. If God creates something,
it is the prerogative of God to create a separate counterbalance to that
something, or to create that something with an internalized dynamic of such
dualism.
This concept runs strikingly through the introduction to John. At first it begins with a primordial creation-story
(which, like the primordial creation-story in Genesis, is not a story at all,
but rather a narratively-framed presentation of a set of conditions):
“In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God,
and the Word was God. The same was in
the beginning with God. All things were
made by him; and without him was not any thing made that was made.”
There is in the above passage no hint of how a course of
events therein might be understood, nor any hint that such analysis would be of
any profit. The above passage leads to
the next, pivotal statement:
“In him was life; and the life was the light of men.”
As I said, the primordial creation-story admits of no
logical analysis, so there is no warrant to imagine that the “life” here
described is “biological” in the strict sense, nor even restricted to a “life”
in Jesus understood directly as a provision for humanity. Jesus acts like fig-trees and mountains are
alive—it would be an act of gross presumption to insist on overturning the
insistent implication of a Creation made by and with the living Son of God—a Creation
as an incomprehensible living totality.
The important point for the present analysis is to see the
above passage as linked to the next, so:
“In him was life; and the life was the light of men. And the light shineth in darkness; and the darkness
comprehended [that is, overpowered] it not.”
We must be reminded here of the analogous passage in Genesis:
“And God saw the light, that it was good: and God divided
the light from the darkness.”
If the light was not divided from the darkness at first, then
it permeated all. To divide the light
from the darkness was to draw out from it darkness—something that we cannot
understand, yet the implication from what little we can understand is that “light”
includes both light and dark, just as the “life” understood as pre-existing the
light includes within itself both life and death. The sovereign creative power of God that brings
dualisms into existence simultaneously reins them in.
If this principle is understood and applied properly, then the
rest of the introduction to John falls into place in our comprehension.
“There was a man sent from God, whose name was John.” This, of course, is the John who said he was
not Elijah, while Jesus said he was indeed Elijah. There ought to be nothing really strange in
this. The “John Chapter One” life in
Jesus is life, and it is also (in our ken) not-life. The light is light, and it is also not-light. John the Baptist is Elijah, and he is also
not-Elijah.
After a brief description of the Baptist as a witness of the
Light, we have:
“That was the true Light, which lighteth every man that cometh
into the world. He was in the world, and
the world was made by him, and the world knew him not.”
To apply the straightforward analysis of which we imagine ourselves
capable (and which we usually presume to be appropriate), we would have to
conclude that the preceding passage is simply untrue. The gospels are full of descriptions of “the
world” in any number of terms (storms, plants, fish, children, crowds,
prospective disciples, prophets, dead people, maladies, even—if you will—demons)
in which Jesus is indeed recognized in such vein as is appropriate to the son
and equal of the Creator God. To use the
analysis I have proposed above, there is no such difficulty, because Jesus
possesses indeed both totalities of the dualism. Jesus is the recognized and the
not-recognized.
The Introduction continues:
“He came unto his own, and his own received him not. But as many as received him, to them gave he
power to become the sons of God, even to them that believe on his name: Which
were born, not of blood, nor of the will of the flesh, nor of the will of man,
but of God.”
The “unto his own” part seems curiously circumspect, if we
are to take it simply as a reference to “the Jews” or to “Judaism.” This is the same gospel that has “the chief
priests of the Jews” say to Pilate, “Write not, The King of the Jews . . . ,”
so we can probably surmise that the “unto his own” part is not meant out of delicacy. We would do well to note that further on in
the Introduction there is:
“For the law was given by Moses, but grace and truth came by
Jesus Christ.”
In the same framework of circumspection as the “unto his own”
part, we can analyze the “law given by Moses” part as potentially more comprehensive
than the idea of “the Jewish Law.” The
notion of the written law as in part a manifestation of a greater “law of the heart”
or some such was not unknown in Jesus’ day (see Paul in Romans.) Moreover, “unto his own” was potentially a malleable
term, applicable in the most restrictive way to a “Judaism” that really did
reflect the majority heritage of Judah as against the more diminished tribes,
and the pivotal ancestor was now Jacob (Israel), and then again now Abraham.
So we have Jesus who was a Jew, and Jesus who was a not-Jew,
much as we have (by his own puzzling query) Jesus who was Son of David and not-Son-of-David. Much of this latter observation is of little
consequence to an analysis of Jesus’ ministry, just as trying to figure out the
primordial creation-stories might also be of little consequence (or little
profit.) There is, however, no warrant
for perfunctorily turning over and casting aside persisting questions about
dualism (which of course involve far more than the discussion here.) Endless publications address the issue of “Why
God Permits Evil.”
We might also, in a more comprehensive vein, draw up lists
of questions about Why God Permits Unsolvable Questions to Exist. We have gotten to the end of the Introduction
to John, and just such a question arises (particularly since we are considering
the Patriarchs):
“No man hath seen God at any time; the only begotten Son,
which is in the bosom of the Father, he hath declared him.”
It is the “at any time” part that lingers—one of the chief
commonalities of the patriarchs and notables of ancient Israel is the phenomenon
of (admittedly fleeting or partial or “typological”) glimpses of God. Here in John the gap and the distinction
between God and his Creation are emphasized, and we would do well to maintain a
respectful distance. I contend, however,
that considerations such as those about “dualisms” and “the sovereignty of God”
in the midst of this discussion are of great importance.
We do not understand dualisms in Creation because we were
not witnesses of Creation, nor is it really the case that Genesis or the other
scriptures describe the act of creation.
What falls to us in description since the creation of Adam is what falls
away from an original state (or divinely-intended original state) that we can
barely begin to imagine. The idea that
the original and ongoing creative acts of God can be understood as dualisms
translatable into our understandings of science or even of everyday experiences
must always be suspect—not least because none of that helps The Problem of Evil. It is probably no surprise that I will put
forth the idea that good and evil are not a duality—that instead they are both
aspects of good, much as life and death are both aspects of life.
What I consider most important, however, is that a lively
approach to such questions can help us remember just how frustratingly primordial
must be any of our attempts to understand our plight. Our origins as a collective people cannot be
understood as a God-designed plan for humanity and its institutions that was
thrown off-course by the Fall. God designed
Creation for Adam (and potentially others) to thrive in unfettered communion
with God. The whole “society” thing is a
reparative process, not a pristine plan.
That much is made plain in Genesis, if we are willing to read it without
presuppositions.
With the Gospel of John and the “No man hath seen God at any
time” passage in mind, we must do better than simply believe that no man hath
seen God (while struggling with Scripture passages that seem to say the
opposite.) “No man hath seen God” is an
attitude of reverence, and it is not well-served by contentions about the character
of God that cannot stand unsparing analysis.
Neither have we any warrant to draw up pictures of God that consist of
characterizations of him setting us this or that institution when we have good
reason to suspect that they were not his “original plan.”
This reverential attitude can also have great practical applications. A certain sophomoric type of American political
analysis harps on the idea (of value in itself) that government is at best a “necessary
evil,” and both a conservative Christian view of man as depraved and a good
Fourth-of-July dose of Israel being chastised for wanting a king can be drawn
up in support. The problem with this
analysis is that it is often yoked to the idea that “the family” was God’s original
plan, and that government intrusion (or fancied government intrusion) upon the
family (read: patriarchal family) is to be avoided at all costs. Of course, the history of anti-governmental “family-based”
communities provide the conscientious observer no lack of examples of why both
family and government are necessary, and are both often evil.
I will not pretend to be unaware, however, how conventional—and scripturally comfortable—analyses of my views will hold me in suspicion. It makes my head swim, indeed, to read what I just wrote: Good and evil are not a duality—instead they are both aspects of good, much as life and death are both aspects of life.
No comments:
Post a Comment